Bad Advertisement?
Are you a Christian?
Online Store:Visit Our Store
| Chapter XXV.—Plato’s knowledge of God’s eternity. PREVIOUS SECTION - NEXT SECTION - HELP
eternity" title="283" id="viii.vi.xxv-p1.2"/>How, then, does Plato
blame Homer for saying that the gods are not inflexible, although, as is
obvious from the expressions used, Homer said this for a useful purpose?
For it is the property of those who expect to obtain mercy by prayer and
sacrifices, to cease from and repent of their sins. For those who think
that the Deity is inflexible, are by no means moved to abandon their
sins, since they suppose that they will derive no benefit from
repentance. How, then, does Plato the philosopher condemn the poet Homer
for saying, “Even the gods themselves are not inflexible,”
and yet himself represent the maker of the gods as so easily turned, that
he sometimes declares the gods to be mortal, and at other times declares
the same to be immortal? And not only concerning them, but also
concerning matter, from which, as he says, it is necessary that the
created gods have been produced, he sometimes says that it is uncreated,
and at other times that it is created; and yet he does not see that he
himself, when he says that the maker of the gods is so easily turned, is
convicted of having fallen into the very errors for which he blames
Homer, though Homer said the very opposite concerning the maker of the
gods. For he said that he spoke thus of himself:—
“For ne’er my promise shall deceive, or fail,
Or be recall’d, if with a nod confirm’d.”2559
But Plato, as it seems, unwillingly entered not these
strange dissertations concerning the gods, for he feared those who were
attached to polytheism. And whatever he thinks fit to tell of all
that he had learned from Moses and the prophets concerning one God, he
preferred delivering in a mystical style, so that those who desired to be
worshippers of God might have an inkling of his own opinion. For being
charmed with that saying of God to Moses, “I am the really
existing,” and accepting with a great deal of thought the brief
participial expression, he understood that God desired to signify to
Moses His eternity, and therefore said, “I am the really
existing;” for this word “existing” expresses not one
time only, but the three—the past, the present, and the future.
For when Plato says, “and which never really is,” he uses the
verb “is” of time indefinite. For the word
“never” is not spoken, as some suppose, of the past, but of
the future time. And this has been accurately understood even by profane
writers. And therefore, when Plato wished, as it were, to interpret to
the uninitiated what had been mystically expressed by the participle
concerning the eternity of God, he employed the following language:
“God indeed, as the old tradition runs, includes the beginning, and
end, and middle of all things.” In this sentence he plainly and
obviously names the law of Moses “the old tradition,”
fearing, through dread of the hemlock-cup, to mention the name of Moses;
for he understood that the teaching of the man was hateful to the Greeks;
and he clearly enough indicates Moses by the antiquity of the tradition.
And we have sufficiently proved from Diodorus and the rest of the
historians, in the foregoing chapters, that the law of Moses is not only
old, but even the first. For Diodorus says that he was the first of all
lawgivers; the letters which belong to the Greeks, and which they
employed in the writing of their histories, having not yet been
discovered. E.C.F. INDEX & SEARCH
|